Oughts and Ends
نویسندگان
چکیده
As this ought, or ought not, expresses some new relation or affirmation, ‗tis necessary that it shou'd be observ'd and explain'd' and at the same time that a reason should be given; for what seems altogether inconceivable, how this new relation can be a deduction from others, which are entirely different from it. Hume never actually asserted what has come to be called ‗Hume's Law': that you cannot validly derive a proposition containing an ‗ought' from propositions stating only what is the case. But he did pose a challenge that many have thought impossible to meet: to analyze ‗ought' purely in terms that are not normative, evaluative, or deontic. It is not difficult to provide plausible analyses of ought-propositions into propositions that state what is the case. For example Reasons-Ought: X ought to φ =(df.) X has more reason to φ than to act in any other way instead; Value-Ought: X ought to φ =(df.) It is better that X φs than that X does anything else instead. These analyses, however, are not constituted wholly of terms that are ‗entirely different' from ‗ought': ‗reasons' and ‗better' are similarly normative, and similarly thought to be in need of analysis or explanation by those who see a need to analyze ‗ought'. Philosophers who follow G. E. Moore in rejecting ‗analytic naturalism' about normative terms deny that any other kind of analytic definition is possible. In a recent statement of this view, Allan Gibbard writes that ―no correct definition can break out of the normative circle, a circle of ought-like terms.‖ (2003, p. 6) I shall propose a theory of the semantics of ‗ought', consisting of six theses, which I call the end-relational theory. This theory is reductive or broadly naturalistic, decomposing ‗ought' into a complex of nonnormative terms or concepts, and is thus a ‗cognitivist' account, although it has a significant expressivist or noncognitivist element. There are many reasons for wanting such a reductive analysis, but I shall not address them here; the case for the theory will be based 2 solely upon its intrinsic theoretical virtues and its plausibility and fit with the data. It claims to be interpretive rather than revisionary: to identify the meaning with which ordinary speakers use the word. It also claims to be exhaustive, capturing all legitimate uses of ‗ought'. This virtue, which distinguishes it from all competing accounts presently finding favour with philosophers, provides the …
منابع مشابه
Ideals and Oughts and the Reliance on Affect versus Substance in Persuasion
Motivation research distinguishes two types of goals: (a) ideals, which relate to people’s hopes, wishes, and aspirations, and (b) oughts, which relate to people’s duties, obligations, and responsibilities. We propose that, in persuasion, the accessibility of ideals increases consumers’ reliance on their subjective affective responses to the ad relative to the substance of the message, whereas ...
متن کاملDynamic Thoughts on Ifs and Oughts
Iffy oughts figure prominently in a variety of paradoxes of deontic logic. A satisfying response to these paradoxes is a non-negotiable component of any adequate semantic story about conditionals and deontic modals. I demonstrate that such a story can be told but doing so requires that we supplement a semantics that pays proper attention to the sensitivity of ifs and oughts to contextual inform...
متن کاملChisholm's Paradox and Conditional Oughts
Since it was presented in 1963, Chisholm’s paradox has attracted constant attention in the deontic logic literature, but without the emergence of any definitive solution. We claim this is due to its having no single solution. The paradox actually presents many challenges to the formalization of deontic statements, including (1) context sensitivity of unconditional oughts, (2) formalizing condit...
متن کاملLecture 2: Kratzer, Poole, Conditionals and Means-End Reasoning ESSLLI’16: Deontic modality: linguistic and logical perspectives on oughts and ends
The formal framework introduced by Kratzer in 1981 is closely related to the work on DSDL in the sixties and seventies, such as the work of Hansson and Lewis discussed in the handout of Lecture 1. Her semantics is therefore sometimes referred to as the Lewis-Kratzer semantics. In the semantics of Kratzer, the preference ordering is not given, but it is constructed from two sets of propositions,...
متن کاملDeontic Modals: Why Abandon the Classical Semantics?
I begin by reviewing classical semantics and the problems presented by normative conflicts. After a brief detour through default logic, I establish some connections between the treatment of conflicts in each of these two approaches, classical and default, and then move on to consider some further issues: priorities among norms, or reasons, conditional oughts, and reasons about reasons.
متن کاملValues as Self-Guides 1 Running Head: VALUES AS SELF-GUIDES Cultural Differences in Values as Self-Guides
Three studies tested whether individualism–collectivism moderates the extent to which values are endorsed as ideal self-guides and ought self-guides, and the consequences for regulatory focus and emotion. Across Studies 1 and 2, individualists endorsed values that are relatively central to the self as stronger ideals than oughts, whereas collectivists endorsed them as ideals and oughts to a sim...
متن کاملذخیره در منابع من
با ذخیره ی این منبع در منابع من، دسترسی به آن را برای استفاده های بعدی آسان تر کنید
عنوان ژورنال:
دوره شماره
صفحات -
تاریخ انتشار 2008